SciELO - Scientific Electronic Library Online

 
vol.36 número2Pesquisas em formação de professores que ensinam matemáticaA integração da tecnologia na planificação de aulas na perspectiva do ensino exploratório: um estudo com futuros professores de matemática índice de autoresíndice de assuntospesquisa de artigos
Home Pagelista alfabética de periódicos  

Serviços Personalizados

Journal

Artigo

Compartilhar


Perspectiva

versão impressa ISSN 0102-5473versão On-line ISSN 2175-795X

Perspectiva vol.36 no.2 Florianopolis abr./jun 2018  Epub 24-Jul-2019

https://doi.org/10.5007/2175-795x.2018v36n2p399 

Artigos

Reaching back to advance: Towards a 21st-century approach to fraction knowledge with the 4A-Instructional Model

Recuando para avançar: rumo a uma abordagem do século XXI para conhecimento de fração com o Modelo-4A de Instrução

Alcanzando hacia atrás para avanzar: Hacia un enfoque del siglo XXI para conocimiento de fracción con el Modelo-4A de Instrucción

1University-Newark, USA


Abstract

In daily life, rational numbers are ever-present and extraordinarily useful. Unfortunately, for teachers and students alike, fractions have proven to be conceptually difficult. We argue that conceptual difficulties of fraction knowledge have two causes: ontological and epistemological. The ontological problem rests on dominant ahistorical theorizations of fractions that are the basis of current curricular proposals. The epistemological challenge of fraction knowledge originates in instructional inattention to fostering learners’ fractional number sense. From a cultural-historical perspective, inspired by theoretical and empirical work of Davydov and Gattegno, we propose ontological and epistemological perspectives as alternatives for the construction of fraction knowledge. Finally, we present a pedagogical instrument—the 4A-Instructional Model—designed to engender learners’ view of themselves as empowered agents of mathematical knowledge.

Keywords:  4A-Instructional Model; Cultural-Historical Perspective; Davydov; Gattegno; Rational Numbers

Resumo

Na vida cotidiana, números racionais estão sempre presentes e são extraordinariamente úteis. Infelizmente, tanto para professores como para estudantes, as frações provaram ser conceitualmente difíceis. Argumentamos que as dificuldades conceituais do conhecimento de frações têm duas causas: ontológica e epistemológica. O problema ontológico baseia-se nas dominantes teorizações ahistóricas das frações que são a base das propostas curriculares atuais. O desafio epistemológico do conhecimento da fração origina-se em desatenção instrucional para possibilitar a produção de sentido para o conceito de número fracionário aos alunos. Do ponto de vista histórico-cultural, inspirado no trabalho teórico e empírico de Davydov e Gattegno, propomos perspectivas ontológicas e epistemológicas como alternativas à construção do conhecimento de frações. Finalmente, apresentamos um instrumento pedagógico—o 4A-Instructional Model—projetado para engendrar a visão dos aprendizes sobre si mesmos como agentes capacitados do conhecimento matemático.

Palavras-chave:  Modelo 4ª de Instrução; Davydov; Gattegno; Números Racionais; Perspectiva Histórico-Cultural

Resumen

En la vida cotidiana, los números racionales están siempre presentes y son extraordinariamente útiles. Desgraciadamente, tanto para profesores como para estudiantes, las fracciones probaron ser conceptualmente difíciles. Argumentamos que las dificultades conceptuales del conocimiento de fracciones tienen dos causas: ontológica y epistemológica. El problema ontológico se basa en las dominantes teorizaciones ahistóricas de las fracciones que son la base de las propuestas curriculares actuales. El desafío epistemológico del conocimiento de la fracción se origina en desatención instruccional para posibilitar la producción de sentido para el concepto de número fraccionario a los alumnos. Desde el punto de vista histórico-cultural, inspirado en el trabajo teórico y empírico de Davydov y Gattegno, proponemos perspectivas ontológicas y epistemológicas como alternativas a la construcción del conocimiento de fracciones. Finalmente, presentamos un instrumento pedagógico-el 4A-Instruccional Model-diseñado para engendrar la visión de los aprendices sobre sí mismos como agentes capacitados del conocimiento matemático.

Palabras clave:  Modelo 4A de Instrucción; Davydov; Gattegno; Números Racionales; Perspectiva Histórico-Cultural

Introduction

Rational numbers, whether represented as fractions, decimals, or percentages, are not only infinite but also ubiquitous. In daily life, they are inescapable in rural, suburban, and urban environments; at home and work; in commerce, sports, and recreation. Whether one is engaged in quotidian or academic pursuits, rational numbers are also useful. The academic and the quotidian utility of rational numbers are connected. Fractions did not originate as an abstract algebraic structure such as an Abelian group with the addition operation1 or as a commutative field with a unit.2 Instead, they emerged to answer questions concerning “how much?”. To answer such a question in practical and material terms, as Gillings (1972/1982) recounts, in Ancient Egypt, land surveyors used rods, poles, and knotted cords of rope to measure lengths and the end-to-end distance of the property. Such measures rarely, if ever, were an exact multiple of the rod, pole, or distance between two knots on a cord; that is, of the unit of measure. We can imagine that at first the measure as approximations to natural numbers was acceptable. However, later, to pay and collect taxes, for instance, more precise measurements were undoubtedly required.

In quotidian and academic endeavors alike, rational numbers are moreover essential. In educational settings, they are so critical that procedural and, especially, conceptual knowledge of fractions are linchpins for success with higher mathematics. For achievement in mathematics beyond the elementary school years, an emerging body of empirical studies in mathematics education is documenting the importance of competence with fractions (Siegler et al., 2011; Bailey et al., 2012; Siegler et al., 2012). However, despite their importance, current research also indicates that students and their teachers indistinguishably lack flexible and conceptual knowledge of fractions (Lamon, 2012; Olanoff et al., 2014).

Conceptual knowledge of mathematics is critical for pleasurable and successful participation in school mathematics and recreational mathematics as well as in fields such as science, technology, and engineering. Policy makers, psychologists, mathematicians, and mathematics education researchers alike recognize both anecdotally and empirically that conceptual knowledge of fractions and, in general, rational numbers constitute a necessary condition for participation and high performance in advanced mathematics (Wu, 2001; Lamon, 2007; National Mathematics Advisory Panel, 2008; Wu, 2009; Bailey et al., 2012; Lamon, 2012; Siegler et al., 2012; Maher e Yankelewitz, 2017). Students who experience conceptual difficulties with fractions not only incorrectly order and operate on them (Maher e Yankelewitz, 2017) but also have poor mathematics achievement and unsuccessful experiences learning higher mathematical topics such as algebra, probability, and calculus (Lamon, 2001; Bailey et al., 2012; Booth e Newton, 2012; Siegler et al., 2012; Depaepe et al., 2015; Torbeyns et al., 2015).

The conceptual deficiency in fraction knowledge among teachers and students coexists with current curriculum standards and textbooks grounded in known ineffective an epistemological notion about fractions that they represent parts of a whole equipartitioned (Ni e Zhou, 2005; Alajmi, 2012). This part/whole notion and its corresponding pedagogical practices are based on an ontological view of fractions.

Fractions are conceptual objects. Their existence in mathematics, that is, their ontology is owed to a theorization of specific human actions that are part of a material historical, cultural practice. There can be different ontological perspectives about a mathematical concept. In the case of fractions, there are mainly two perspectives: partitioning and measurement. From the partitioning perspective, the existence of fractions emerges from the division of divisible things, a unit equally subdivided and a certain number of them distinguished. Whereas, from a measurement perspective, the ontology of fractions arises from problems of measuring quantities, which is the multiplicative comparison of pairs of magnitudes. Moreover, based on its ontological commitment, each perspective defines fractions differently.

The dominant perspective in school mathematics is the partitioning view that privileges a so-called part/whole notion or subconstruct (Lamon, 2012). Within the partitioning perspective, researchers generally agree that there are four other subconstructs—quotient, ratio, operator, and measure—and that constitute a complete knowledge of fractions (Kieren, 1980; Behr et al., 1983; Freudenthal, 1983; Vergnaud, 1983; Kieren, 1993; Lamon, 2001). Despite decades of reforms in mathematics education policy, curriculum standards, and textbooks, students still have serious difficulties conceptualizing fractions and rational numbers (Martin et al., 2007; National Mathematics Advisory Panel, 2008; Alajmi, 2012; Lin et al., 2013; Siegler e Lortie-Forgues, 2015; Maher & Yankelewitz, 2017).

Contributing to difficulties in learning fraction is its multifaceted construct. For instance, a fraction 34 can be conceived as a part of a whole (three out of four equal parts), as a quotient (three divided by four), an operator (three quarters of a quantity), a ratio (three objects to four objects), and finally as a measure (iterating the unit fraction, 14 , three times on a number line). Historically and currently, one ontological approach has dominated: the view that fractions are parts of wholes (Davydov & Tsvetkovich, 1991; Morris, 2000). That is, the symbol, a/b , represents parts of a whole, where b indicates the number of equal parts into which a whole has been partitioned, and a designates the number of parts of interest. Given a part/whole interpretation, the fraction, 34 , is understood to be three parts out of four parts. Relying only on this interpretation of fractions limits students’ understanding (Lamon, 2012). For instance, in Figure 1, do the shaded portions represent 32 of 1, 32 of 2, 34 of 1, or something else?

(Source: Gattegno e Hoffman, 1976)

Figure 1 What fraction do the shaded portions represent? 

Given the dominant part/whole ontological interpretation of fractions, as Gattegno and Hoffman (1976) argue with presenting Figure 1, can students be faulted for thinking that the shaded circles in Figure 1 represent 32 of 2? Students who only work with limited types of visual representations, for example, area models like circles divided into equal-sized pieces, may develop limited strategies, such as counting the number of pieces rather than assessing the relationship of the part(s) to a whole or unit. Moreover, conceiving of fractions as “parts of a whole,” students have difficulty making sense of the fractions where the numerator is larger than the denominator such as 74 and conceding that a fraction is a number, not just part of something (Tucker, 2008).

Corroborating observations of other researchers about the dominant ontological perspective (for example, Kerslake, 1986; Behr et al., 1992; Tzur, 1999; Wu, 2009), Lamon (2001) emphasizes that “mathematically and psychologically, the part/whole interpretation of fraction is not sufficient as a foundation for the system of rational numbers” (p. 150). Nevertheless, a critical gap in the knowledge base persists concerning what alternative subconstruct or ontological perspective overcomes the insufficiency of the dominant perspective and facilitates robust conceptual understanding of fractions.

A complete theory and effective framework for teaching and learning rational numbers are needed (Lamon, 2007). This is especially true since “students’ knowledge of fractions … predicts their mathematics achievement in high school, above and beyond the contributions of their knowledge of whole-number addition, subtraction, and multiplication; verbal and nonverbal IQ; working memory; family education; and family income” (Siegler et al., 2012, p. 695).

In mathematics education, research on students’ learning of fractions and operations on fractions has been based on two ontological perspectives: partitioning and measurement. The partitioning perspective views a fraction as a relation established between parts of a whole equipartitioned. This ontological perspective is rooted in a belief that counting is the basis for arithmetic and has led to the commonly accepted part/whole conception of fractions (Schmittau, 2004). Indeed, it is how the Common Core State Standards (National Governors Association Center for Best Practices e Council of Chief State School Officers, 2010) suggests introducing factions in the elementary school grades. Nevertheless, research indicates that this perspective seriously limits the robustness of students’ understanding of fractions (Kerslake, 1986). It tends to support the erroneous idea that a positive fraction is composed of two different natural numbers and impedes understanding of improper fractions (Tzur, 1999). While research on fraction knowledge within the partitioning perspective has yielded valuable insights into cognitive issues of fraction learning (see for example, Dienes, 1967; Kieren, 1976; 1980; Behr et al., 1984; Mack, 1990; Kieren, 1993; Mack, 1995; Behr et al., 1997; Tzur, 1999; Lamon, 2007; 2012; Hunt et al., 2016; Patahuddin et al., 2017), a critical limitation to fractions research has been its ontological foundation, the partitioning perspective. Little sustained research has investigated the known alternative ontological basis for fraction knowledge, the measurement perspective.

Reaching back historically

Before indicating research on the measurement ontology, it is instructive to consider why the partitioning perspective has dominated curricular approaches to fraction knowledge. As Schmittau (2003) explains the World is full of things which are countable and, interacting in the World, children participate in inherited cultural practices that involve counting. Consequently, children begin formal schooling with knowledge of counting and properties of counting numbers. In Vygotskian terms, through their counting practices, children develop spontaneous rather than scientific knowledge of counting numbers and their properties. Since dominant educational theory suggests, as Schmittau (2003) notes, that “children must construct their own concepts, what better basis could there be on which to build future mathematical understanding than children’s own spontaneous counting concepts?” (p. 226). Counting does generate positive integers but not fractions or irrational numbers. Formally, mathematics defines fractions as the quotient of two integers, a/b , such that b0 . Since this understanding of fractions is not an entry point to fraction knowledge for children, educators devise physical and visual representations such as area models and equipartition the models to illustrate fractions as the ratio of the positive integers formed. However, its formal mathematical definition and the pedagogical practices of constructing equipartitioned visual models are unrelated conceptually to the material origin of fractions.

Fractions emerged 4,000 years or more ago in the social practice of measuring quantities. In a chapter on the essential nature of mathematics, the Soviet-era mathematician, physicist, and philosopher, A. D. Aleksandrov3 (1963), locates the origin of fractions in the early interaction between geometry and arithmetic.

In general, the measurement of any magnitude combines calculations with some specific operation which is characteristic of this sort of magnitude.… But in the process of measurement it turns out, generally speaking, that the chosen unit is not contained in the measured magnitude an integral number of times, so that a simple calculation of the number of units in not sufficient. It becomes necessary to divide up the unit of measurement in order to express the magnitude more accurately by parts of the unit; that is, no longer by whole numbers but by fractions. It was in this way that fractions actually arose, as is shown by an analysis of the historical and other data. They arose from the division and comparison of continuous magnitudes; in other words, from measurement. The first magnitudes to be measured were geometric, namely lengths, areas of fields, and volumes of liquids or friable materials, so that in the earliest appearances of fractions we see the mutual action of arithmetic and geometry. This interaction leads to the appearance of an important new concept, namely fractions, as an extension of the concept of number from whole numbers to fractional numbers…. Fractions did not arise, and could not arise from the division of whole numbers, since only whole objects are counted by whole numbers. Three men, three arrows, and so forth, all these make sense, but two-thirds of a man and even two-thirds of an arrow are senseless concepts; even three separate thirds of an arrow will not kill a deer, for this it is necessary to have a whole arrow. (p. 24-25; original emphasis)

Aleksandrov argues that the historical emergence of fractions is neither connected to the idea of whole number division nor multiples of unit fractions. His argument hinges on the fundamental distinction between a unit used for counting and for measuring. He writes: “only whole objects are counted by whole numbers” (my emphasis). That is, when counting, the chosen unit is indivisible; whereas, when measuring, the chosen unit is divisible. This critical conceptual difference notwithstanding, the ontological presentation of fractions as emerging from the quotient of whole numbers—parts of an equipartioned whole—or as multiples of unit fractions displayed on a numberline are the bases of contemporary proposals for introducting fractions (See, for example, Common core state standards for mathematics, Common Core State Standards Initiative, 2010). Instead, Aleksandrov posits that the specific interaction between arithmetic and geometry from which the need for fractions emerged was the social practice of measuring magnitudes of lengths, areas, and volumes. These practices were part of the social life of ancient Africans in Egypt.4 For instance, they employed them to construct pyramids more than 1000 years (5000 years ago) before the famous Ahmes and Moscow papyri were scribed (Struik, 1967/1948; Resnikoff & Wells Jr., 1984/1973), both of which evidence Egyptians’ invention of fractions and operations on fractions. Fractions arising from measuring practices are intertwined with land surveying. According to Herodotus, a Greek historian, who wrote the nine-volume magnum opus, The Histories, in the fifth century BCE, the Egyptian practice of land surveying gave rise to ‘geometry,’ a derivative of an Ancient Greek word meaning measuring the earth (Roque, 2012). The ancient Egyptian measuring practices that begot fractions and geometry simultaneously caused geometry and fractions to be mutually constituted.

Though fractions continued to be used in later civilizations such as Mesopotamia, Greece, China, and India, as Davydov and Tsvetkovich (1991) note, it was only in the 12th century CE, just 900 years ago, that they were considered as numbers and then finally, in the 19th century CE, laws for operating with fractions were formally elaborated. By the time rules for operating with fractions were established, fractions had become (1) conceptually distant from their concrete “object source” in measuring quantities and (2) an abstract number equal in status with natural numbers (Courant & Robbins, 1996/1941; Davydov e Tsvetkovich, 1991).

From a Vygotskian or cultural-historical perspective, understanding the ontology of a mathematical concept starts with considering its historical origin in social practices and the conscious mathematical theorization that led to its development. Measurement as the source for fraction knowledge has been the object of limited research efforts. As the material source of both whole numbers and fractions, measurement has been theoretically and pedagogically investigated by Brousseau (Brousseau et al., 2004) as well as Davydov and others who have adapted Davydov’s curriculum (Davydov & Tsvetkovich, 1991; Morris, 2000; Schmittau & Morris, 2004; Dougherty e Venenciano, 2007). Different from “children’s spontaneously constructed counting structures, the [Davydov] curriculum develops the concept of a number as the ratio of some quantity to another quantity that is used as the unit” (Morris, 2000). Morris (2000) investigated the adoption of this approach to fraction learning with a group of fourth-graders (9- to10-year olds) who were learning about fractions as numbers. Two results of her analysis are particularly important. First, “literal symbolism proved to be unproblematic for the children. It appears to assist the instructor in changing the focus of instruction from numerical computation to reasoning about quantitative relationships” (Morris, 2000). Second, “working only with graph paper and a pencil [, children derived their own] representations … [that] assisted them in keeping track of abstract relationships, and forced them to re-think these relationships with each new application” (Morris, 2000). It is possible to provide students with manipulative materials, such as Cuisenaire rods (described below), so that when writing about relations among their measured lengths, they use “literal symbolism.” Moreover, learners will use the manipulative materials to talk about relations they perceive, abstract, and talk about and later indicate those relations in writing.

Davydov (Davydov & Tsvetkovich, 1991), Morris (2000), Schmittau and Morris (2004), Brousseau (Brousseau et al., 2004), and others (Dougherty & Venenciano, 2007) have contributed to knowledge about affordances of a measurement perspective for whole number and fraction knowledge. Their work raises questions about how to use this perspective to teach fraction knowledge so that students, younger than fourth graders, develop number sense about fractions that in turn will provide a conceptual scaffold for students to learn subsequently about fractions as numbers and operations on fractions.

Looking forward ontologically and epistemologically

In response to this conceptual gap in the literature, we propose that a measurement perspective shapes positively early elementary students’ (6 to 8 year olds) development of number sense about fractions through studying fractions as measures and issues of magnitude, order, and equivalence. Informed by theoretical work of Davydov and Tsvetkovich (1991), developed and implemented during the era of the Union of Soviet Socialist Republics, we propose particular ways to conceptualize the ontology of fractions and the epistemology of fraction knowledge. We distinguish two different levels of abstraction to arrive at whole numbers and fractions. First, whole number knowledge requires abstracting quantity from the qualitative characteristics of objects and later being concerned with magnitude, order, equality, and inequality of these quantities. Second, knowledge of fractions requires another level of abstraction. It necessitates abstracting quantitative relations between quantities followed by recognizing magnitude, order, equality, and inequality of these quantitative relations. This second level of abstraction is the cognitive challenge and opportunity of our perspective on fraction learning.

The ontological perspective of our measurement perspective posits the following:

    1. A fraction is a relation between two quantities. The relation is a multiplicative comparison between two quantities: Suppose A and B are two objects that have a common extensive attribute such as length expressed as quantities with a common unit, u, where A equals a units of u and B equals b units of u. Then, in the expression, a/b , b is understood to measure a and a/b is the relation of a measured by b . The quantities a and b have the same unit of measure, which is something less than or equal to b . The common extensive attribute can also be area, volume, mass, weight, or the count of a countable discrete set. This is also known as the definition of a fraction-as-number.

    2. A theorization of a fractions-as-measure: In the material realm, suppose two objects, A and B , have a common measurable attribute such as length with a common unit, u, where A equals a units of u and B equals b units of u. The length of one object A is the fraction a/b of the length of the other object, B . As such, the fraction a/b describes a relation between the two objects, A and B , and the relation is a multiplicative comparison, A equals a/b of B , as one quantity is a multiplier of the other. The symbolic representation of a fraction-as-measure is this: ab of or, equivalently, ab× . It represents a measure of A in relation to B .

Based on this ontological perspective, we posit the following epistemological position about how fraction knowledge can emerge:

    1. The study of fractions contains two components: fractions-as-measures and fractions-as-numbers.

    2. Fractional number sense is developed through the study of fractions-as-measures. Fractions-as-measures provide material and theoretical foundation for the later study of fractions-as-numbers and operations on fractions.

Fractional number sense is a special case of number sense. In general, number sense emerges before children begin formal schooling (Jordan et al., 2010); in contrast to those who do not, children who possess foundational knowledge of whole numbers are positioned to benefit from mathematical experiences and instruction of elementary school (Baroody et al., 2006). Kalchman et al. (2001) provide the following list of characteristics what number sense includes: “(a) fluency in estimating and judging magnitude, (b) ability to recognize unreasonable results, (c) flexibility when mentally computing, (d) ability to move among different representations and to use the most appropriate representations” (p. 2). Knowledge of number concepts and skills with mathematics procedures appear to be mutually supportive, each facilitating the development of the other area (Rittle-Johnson et al., 2001). In contrast to whole number knowledge, students of early elementary school age (5- to 9-years old) have relatively underdeveloped fractional number sense. By the time instruction in fraction begins in third grade (8- to 9-years old), students, at most, have ideas of one-half, one-third, and perhaps one-fourth. Linguistically, in English, they have difficulty pronouncing fractional numbers, not hearing or producing the ordinal endings for unit and non-unit fractions. For instance, for the fraction, 24 , instead of two-fourths, students erroneously say “two fours.”

In addition to the need to develop oral fluency with fractional names, early elementary students would benefit from developing number sense about the magnitude, order, equivalence, and inequality of fractions, starting with fractions-as-measures. To implement our ontological and epistemological perspective that we presented penultimate paragraph requires tools such as manipulative materials that have an extensive attribute that can be used to compare the attribute among different instantiations of the tool. We have chosen to use Cuisenaire rods (see Figure 2). The ingenious inventor of these rods, Emile-Georges Cuisenaire (1891-1975), a Belgian schoolteacher, imbued them with functional and interesting correspondences between color and length. Rods of the same color are the same length and, conversely, rods of the same length have the same color. A length that is the double of another is also darker in tone. The smallest rod is a neutral color, usually referred to as “white.” Rods that are equivalent in length to two, four, and eight white rods have pigments with an affinity to the red family (purple and brown). Rods equivalent in length to 3, 6, and 9 white rods are colored respectively green, dark green, and blue, while rods equivalent to 5 and 10 white rods are yellow and orange. The rod whose length has the distinction of being relatively prime to rods of all other lengths in the set is colored black. Interestingly, the two primary colors, red and yellow, mix to make orange, which parallel the fact that the two nontrivial factors of the orange rod (equivalent in length to 10 white rods) are the red rod (equivalent in length to 2 white rods) and yellow rod (equivalent in length to 5 white rods).

Figure 2 Cuisenaire rods, ten different sizes and colors, arranged in a “staircase” formation. 

The Cuisenaire rods are a simple but inventive collection of physical materials (wooden or, now, plastic parallelepipeds) or manipulatives with which children can quickly become familiar. Being familiar with manipulatives in mathematics learning is an important first step in their effective use (Willingham, 2009). To become familiar with Cuisenaire rods and relations among them, children need to engage in both free play and structured tasks in which they attend to two characteristics of the rods: the tangible (length) and the visible (color). Because of their simplicity, while students work on mathematics tasks, Cuisenaire rods do not generate high extraneous cognitive load (Sweller, 1994; Sweller et al., 1998). As such, they allow students to focus mainly on acquiring awarenesses about relations among the rods, which yield ideas about whole numbers, fractions, and operations on them. However, as Meira (1998) underscores, instructional representations such as Cuisenaire rods have no inherent transparency, they are “meaningful only with respect to learners’ activities.”

With Cuisenaire rods, students can build mathematical meaning and mental images about fractions and operations on fractions. Teachers direct their students’ attention to simple but powerful visualizations of fractions: measuring lengths of Cuisenaire rods and identifying relations among the rods. The rods are straightforward, physical, and cognitive models of fractions. Students can evoke images them to think about fractions, relations among fractions, and operations on fractions. They enable students to build personal and, therefore, meaningful ideas about fractions and connect them to other mathematical ideas (Ma, 1999). Students can connect different mathematical ideas when their understanding builds on basic ideas and when they use simple, manipulative models systematically (Ma, 1999; Willingham, 2009).

To understand fractions and other topics of school mathematics, there are two necessary approaches to the idea of number and operations on numbers: partitioning and measurement. First, the partitioning approach involves counting, the naming of an ordered sequence of numerals or using these numerals to label, without omission or duplication, separate and distinct items of a collection such as children on a soccer field or turtles on a beach. Second, the measurement approach involves measuring, comparing a continuous quantity to a standard unit such as determining the straight-line distance from one end of a soccer field to its other end or the yearly amount of rainwater collected in a barrel. Counting is used to answer the question, “How many?”; while measuring answers the question, “How much?”

Looking forward pedagogically

To avoid epistemological flaws and inadequacies of the partitioning perspective, we use an approach based on measurement (Davydov & Tsvetkovich, 1991; Gattegno, 2009/1960). A prime example of an extensive quantity is length. With this, then, how does one teach about fractions from a measurement approach, using Cuisenaire rods? This is the subject an instructional model that we propose, the 4A-Instructional Model. Table 1 below presents the model, which consists of four phases for implementing a pedagogical approach, the subordination of the teaching of mathematics to students’ learning5, using Cuisenaire rods. In this approach, an instructional unit is often longer than a single class meeting. The sequence consists of a coherent, flexible sequence of tasks intended to enable students to educate their awareness about ideas of a mathematical topic.

Table 1  6Four phases of our instructional model containing 13 potential instructional activities for implementing the subordination of the teaching of mathematics to students’ learning, using Cuisenaire rods. 

Actual
Actions
1. Engage the motor and mental powers of students (manipulate, observe, listen, see, hear, abstract, compare, sequence, stress and ignore…). Instruct them to manipulate rods in particular ways so that through their actions on the rods they perceive target relations among the rods.
2. Introduce mathematical language, comparing it, if necessary, to the non-mathematical language that students use, and provide students with opportunities to practice talking mathematically about what they actually perform and perceive with the rods.
3. Have students create their own rod situations that correspond to what is being worked on.
4. Have students talk, draw, and write about what they learn and provide opportunities for practice.
Virtual
Actions
5. Engage students in virtual action: manipulating mental images of the rods in ways like what students performed in actual action.
6. Have students create without rods their own mathematical situations that correspond to what is being worked on.
7. Have students talk and write about what they learn and provide opportunities for practice.
Actions
Written
8. Introduce writing mathematical expressions and equations that represent what students can already perform orally and virtually and provide opportunities for practice with the rods available.
9. Have students create expressions or equations with or without rods available.
10. Have students talk and write about what they learn and provide opportunities for practice.
Actions
Formalized
11. Formalize symbolically or as a definition the mathematical ideas, concepts, and procedures that have been the basis of students’ actual and virtual mathematical manipulations with the rods.
12. Have students talk and write about their understanding of their mathematical ideas in formal, symbolic or definitional statements.
13. Provide opportunities for students to practice their formalized, symbolic or definitional rendition of what they have done with rods.

Source: Elaborated by the author.

The criterion for moving from one phase to another is students’ fluent facility with the manipulative actions, verbal and symbolic language, mental actions, and ideas of an instructional phase. That is, for a given instructional objective, while working in the Actual Actions phase as soon as students evidence that they are comfortable with the associated rod manipulations, talking about what they are doing and perceiving, and can perform actions nearly without the rods, then it is time to move to the second phase Virtual Actions. Once in this phase, when students exhibit their ability to respond mentally and fluently to tasks from the actual actions phase without physically manipulating rods, then it is appropriate to transition to the Actions-Written phase, where they will work symbolically on actions with which they already have both actual and virtual facility.

The fourth phase, Actions Formalized, is a culminating phase where the mathematical ideas that students constructed in the first three phases are discussed and written using formal, symbolic language. This is the phase, for example, where students use algorithms to represent formally what have done in the previous three phases. In this way, an algorithm is experienced as an encapsulation or symbolic trace of meaningful mathematical actions (Schmittau, 2003).

Each of the four phases of our instructional model occasions opportunities for formative and summative assessments. In each phase, teachers hear and observe what students do and say and, in response to either form of evaluation, adjust their instructional intentions.

Theoretical and empirical underpinnings of the 4A-Instructional Model

It is crucial to reveal the research basis for the epistemological perspective that informs the 4A-Instructional Model. The model assumes that individuals construct knowledge by actively relating of new information to their personal experience and their current frameworks for making sense of that experience (Gattegno, 1973). It also presupposes that though individuals construct their own knowledge, it is accomplished through activities carried out socially (Vygotsky, 1978/1930). In the first phases of the 4A-Instructional Model, oral language and talk are given primacy over symbolic writing. As Oakes et al. (1997) note, talk “is the medium in which meaning is most readily and ubiquitously negotiated” (p. 2). Mathematics learning happens through communication in a social context about objects and relations among the objects (Gattegno, 1987). The activity of doing mathematics involves employing speech genres (explanation, argumentation, and so on) and mathematical inscriptions (numerals, operators, graphs, geometric figures, notations, and so forth). Our 4A-Instructional Model suggests that for mathematics learning, speaking and writing need to occur at distinct moments. In the trajectory of human history and development, hearing and talking precede reading and writing. Similarly, for mathematics instruction, reading and writing mathematics should follow facility with hearing and talking mathematically (Gattegno, 1973; Bezuk & Cramer, 1989; Moses & Cobb, 2001). Intentionally and distinctly, our instructional model first works on hearing and talking mathematically (Actual and Virtual Actions) and then on reading and writing mathematics (Actions Written and Formalized). This approach also minimizes the cognitive load (Sweller, 1994) of recalling and attending to mathematical conventions when expressing mathematical ideas in written form before having a secure understanding of these ideas. We recognize that written mathematical numerals and symbols are not mathematical ideas but rather merely written expressions of such ideas. In the first two phases, students first engage with building their conceptual ideas and then, in the latter two phases, approach how to express their ideas in writing and finally encapsulated symbolically or as a definition.

In the first two phases, spoken words for fractions and mathematical operations such as “five-fourths of,” “five-fourths of four-ninths,” and “five-ninths” are used and only in the third phase are written symbols like 54× , 54×49 , and 59 introduced. There are several reasons for this pedagogical perspective. Students learn by interacting with themselves and others mediated by natural language—talking, listening, and observing (Gattegno, 1973; Vygotsky, 1978/1930; Zack & Graves, 2001). It is critical for students to talk and use mathematical language to appropriate the words and the associated ideas. It is important for students to discuss tasks and ideas and to question one another, negotiate meaning, clarify their understanding, and make their ideas comprehensible to their partners. During collaborative tasks, students practice and use mathematical language. Their understanding grows as they express themselves to their partners and, thereby, reflect on their ideas and learning. To encourage students to talk with partners, teachers use several classroom collaborative structures, such as reciprocal teaching, solve and discuss, partner discussions, and so on, Moreover, talking before writing reduces cognitive load. Students work first on talking about actions and perceptions related to their rod manipulations and, once they have fluency with their articulation, then they can focus on using notational and other symbolic forms to represent what they already know and can do.

What students can already do meaningfully and comfortably is evidenced as they transition from the Actual-Actions phase into and throughout the Virtual-Actions phase. In this phase, without manipulating the rods, students express to themselves and others actions they performed previously in the Actual-Actions phase. Gattegno (1957) emphasizes the importance of this phase when he observes that if students “are to become mathematicians the actual actions must be replaced by virtual ones” (p. 14). Corroborating this position, Davydov (1990) notes that “students should pass gradually and in good time from object-related actions to performing them on a mental plane” (p. 174). To support students’ object-related actions being performed mentally, Virtual-Actions replace Actual-Actions. Virtual mental actions may lead students to develop visuospatial strategies. Such strategies resorting to imaginary rods and rod configurations may be the mechanism that underlies students’ ability to create mentally and articulate orally valid fractional statements about fractions-as-measure magnitudes, order, equivalence, and inequalities.7 Achieving facility in this Virtual-Actions phase is the foundational underpinning for the two subsequent phases, Written and Formalized Actions. Without this facility, the sustainable construction of, for example, the Actions-Written phase is compromised and, instead of relational understanding, students inevitably must rely on memory and procedural mechanisms.

Teachers implement our 4A-Instructional Model in educational settings. These settings are shaped by society’s social, political, and economic context. Within this multifaceted context, students interact verbally in mathematical activity using informal and academic language to make sense of mathematical objects and relations among these objects (see Figure 3). As students interact, they are supported to use academic language to describe to themselves and others what they notice as they manipulate Cuisenaire rods as well as to explain and provide evidence of relations they notice. They are also encouraged to use academic language to justify consequences of the relations and investigate conjectures. This phase is the Actual-Action phase and serves as a foundation for all the other phases (see Figure 3). Before moving to the second phase, students need to develop a secure understanding of how to perform specific actions on rods and relate that to mathematical relations and ideas. Also, students need to acquire fluent ways to talk about these mathematical actions, relations, and ideas.

Figure 3 The 4A-Instructional context and process of students’ unfolding mathematical activities facilitated by the subordination of teaching to learning. 

During the last three phases, students limit their use of physical objects while investigating mathematical ideas. In the second phase, Virtual Actions, they start with visualizing their actions on rods and, in the third and fourth phases, Actions Written and Actions Formalized, use mathematical symbols and notation to write about actions they know how to perform and then formalize these actions in symbolic or definitional form. Nevertheless, during these last three phases, it is imperative to allow students to revisit the Actual-Action phase and work with rods to investigate certain ideas. When students find it necessary to revisit the Actual-Action phase, it does not mean that they are regressing, it indicates that they are making sense of new situations or differently of familiar ones (Carpenter et al., 2015). Teachers may also invite students to use rods to investigate and talk about certain mathematical ideas so that students perceive or work on connections between the Actual-Actions phase and other phases.

Other instructional strategies ask students to represent their ideas in writing early, while they are manipulating objects and trying to make sense of mathematical ideas. This strategy does not allow students to immerse fully in the mathematical relations embodied in their manipulations of objects. Other instructional strategies do not allow students to act on objects before writing; students are asked to manipulate symbols in writing. In this type of mathematics instructional strategy, students do not learn about mathematical ideas and relations among them. Instead, they memorize rules for manipulating symbols and how to express their results in ways that are acceptable by their teache

1A mathematical structure, G, is a group if it consists of a set of elements along with an operation, *, that combines any two elements to form a third element of the set and that satisfies four conditions, called the group axioms, namely closure, associativity, identity and inverse. The group, G,*, is called commutative or Abelian if the operation, *, is commutative.

2A mathematical structure, F, is a field if +, −, ×, and ÷ satisfy their ‘usual properties.’ Suppose a, b, c F . For addition, closure: a + b gives a result in F ; associative: a + b + c gives one, unique result, regardless of whether we first evaluate a + b or b + c; commutative: a + b = b + a; identity: we can find an element 0 ∈ F such that a + 0 = a, 0 + a = a; inverse: we can find −a F . For multiplication, closure: a × b gives a result in F ; associative: a × b × c gives one, unique result, regardless of whether we first evaluate a × b or b × c; commutative: a × b = b × a; identity: we can find and element 1∈ F such that a × 1 = a, 1 × a = a; distributive: a × (b + c) = a × b + a × c. Subtraction is merely the addition of the inverse. For division, multiplicative inverse: we can find an element a1 F .

3According to the 2005 version of his book, Convex Polyhedra (Springer), Aleksandr Danilovich Aleksandrov (1912-1999) was awarded the Stalin State Prize in 1942, the Lobachevsky prize in 1952, and the Euler Golden Medal in 1992.

4That Egyptians engaged in these mathematical practices is also corroborated by recent historical analysis. See, for instance, Roque (2012).

5The phrase, “the subordination of teaching to learning,” refers to a general pedagogical perspective that Gattegno (1970d) advocates based on research on how children learn (see also, Gattegno, 1973). For further insight into Caleb Gattegno and his relationship to mathematics education, see Powell (2007).

7This hypothesis is supported by recent neuroscientific studies concerning the outcome of abacus-based mental calculation training and its positive effects on calculation ability and consequently on executive function and neural efficiency (Wang et al., 2017).

6Table 1 is an elaborated adaptation of a diagram presented in Catir and Wheeler (1973), where the authors depict their view of the unfolding of mathematical activity.

References

ALAJMI, A. H. How do elementary textbooks address fractions? A review of mathematics textbooks in the USA, Japan, and Kuwait. Educational Studies in Mathematics, v. 79, n. 2, p. 239-261, 2012. ISSN 00131954, 15730816. Disponível em: <http://www.jstor.org.proxy.libraries.rutgers.edu/stable/41413109>. [ Links ]

ALEKSANDROV, A. D. A general view of mathematics. In: ALEKSANDROV, A. D.;KOLMOGOROV, A. N., et al (Ed.). Mathematics: Its content, methods, and meaning. Cambridge, MA: Massachusetts Institute of Technology, v.1, 1963. p.1-64. [ Links ]

BAILEY, D. H. et al. Competence with fractions predicts gains in mathematics achievement. Journal of Experimental Child Psychology, v. 113, n. 3, p. 447-455, 11// 2012. ISSN 0022-0965. Disponível em: <http://www.sciencedirect.com/science/article/pii/S0022096512001063>. [ Links ]

BAROODY, A. J.; LAI, M.-L.; MIX, K. S. The development of young children's early number and operation sense and its implications for early childhood education. In: SPODEK, B. e SARACHO, O. (Ed.). Handbook of research on the education of young children. Mahwah, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates, 2006. p.187-221. [ Links ]

BEHR, M. J. et al. Rational number, ratio and proportion. In: GROWS, D. A. (Ed.). Handbook on research on mathematics teaching and learning. New York: Macmillan, 1992. p.296-333. [ Links ]

BEHR, M. J. et al. Conceptual Units Analysis of Preservice Elementary School Teachers' Strategies on a Rational-Number-as-Operator Task. Journal for Research in Mathematics Education, v. 28, n. 1, p. 48-69, 1997. ISSN 00218251, 19452306. Disponível em: <http://www.jstor.org.proxy.libraries.rutgers.edu/stable/749663>. [ Links ]

BEHR, M. J. et al. Rational number concepts. In: LESH, R. e LANDAU, M. (Ed.). Acquisition of mathematical concepts and processes. New York: Academic, 1983. p.91-125. [ Links ]

BEHR, M. J. et al. Order and equivalence of rational numbers: A clinical teaching experiment. Journal for Research in Mathematics Education, v. 5, n. 5, p. 321-341, 1984. [ Links ]

BEZUK, N.; CRAMER, K. Teaching about fractions: What, when, and how? In: TRAFTON, P. R. e SHULTE, A. P. (Ed.). New directions for elementary school mathematics: 1989 Yearbook. Reston, VA: National Council of Teachers of Mathematics, 1989. p.156-167. [ Links ]

BOOTH, J. L.; NEWTON, K. J. Fractions: Could they really be the gatekeeper’s doorman? Contemporary Educational Psychology, v. 37, n. 4, p. 247-253, 10// 2012. ISSN 0361-476X. Disponível em: <http://www.sciencedirect.com/science/article/pii/S0361476X12000392>. [ Links ]

BROUSSEAU, G.; BROUSSEAU, N.; WARFIELD, V. Rationals and decimals as required in the school curriculum: Part 1: Rationals as measurement. The Journal of Mathematical Behavior, v. 23, n. 1, p. 1-20, // 2004. ISSN 0732-3123. Disponível em: <http://www.sciencedirect.com/science/article/pii/S0732312303000683>. [ Links ]

CARPENTER, T. P. et al. Children's mathematics: Cognitively guided instruction. 2. Portsmouth, NH: Heinemann, 2015. ISBN 0325001375. [ Links ]

CATIR, Z.; WHEELER, D. Notes on the Gattegno approach to mathematics. New York: Educational Solutions, 1973. [ Links ]

COMMON CORE STATE STANDARDS INITIATIVE. Common core state standards for mathematics National Governors Association Center for Best Practices, Council of Chief State School Officers 2010. [ Links ]

COURANT, R.; ROBBINS, H. What is mathematics?: An elementary approach to ideas and methods. 2nd revised by Ian Steward, Oxford: New York, 1996/1941. [ Links ]

CUISENAIRE, G.; GATTEGNO, C. Numbers in colour: A new method of teaching the process of arithmetic to all level of the Primary School. London: Hienemann, 1954. [ Links ]

DAVYDOV, V. V. E. Types of generalization in instruction: Logical and psychological problems in the structuring of school curricula. Reston: National Council of Teachers of Mathematics, 1990. Disponível em: <https://www.google.com/search?client=safari&rls=en&q=Types+of+generalization+in+instruction:+Logical+andpsychological+problems+in+the+structuring+of+school+curricula.&ie=UTF-8&oe=UTF-8>. [ Links ]

DAVYDOV, V. V. E.; TSVETKOVICH, Z. H. The object sources of the concept of fractions. In: DAVYDOV, V. V. e STEFFE, L. P. (Ed.). Soviet studies in mathematics education. Volume 6. Psychological abilities of primary school children in learning mathematics. Reston, VA: National Council of Teachers of Mathematics, 1991. p.86-147. [ Links ]

DEPAEPE, F. et al. Teachers' content and pedagogical content knowledge on rational numbers: A comparison of prospective elementary and lower secondary school teachers. Teaching and Teacher Education, v. 47, p. 82-92, 4// 2015. ISSN 0742-051X. Disponível em: <http://www.sciencedirect.com/science/article/pii/S0742051X14001668>. [ Links ]

DIENES, Z. P. Fractions: An operational approach. New York: Herder and Herder, 1967. [ Links ]

DOUGHERTY, B. J.; VENENCIANO, L. C. H. Measure Up for Understanding. Teaching Children Mathematics, v. 13, n. 9, p. 452-456, 2007. ISSN 10735836. Disponível em: <http://www.jstor.org.proxy.libraries.rutgers.edu/stable/41198995>. [ Links ]

FREUDENTHAL, H. Didactical phenomenology of mathematical structures. Boston: D. Reidel, 1983. [ Links ]

GATTEGNO, C. Teaching mathematics in an expanding economy—I. Reading: Cuisenaire, 1957. [ Links ]

______. Gattegno mathematics textbook 4: Fractions, decimals, and percentages. New York: Educational Solutions, 1970a. [ Links ]

______. Gattegno mathematics text-book 2: Study of numbers up to 1,000; The four operations. New York: Educational Solutions, 1970b. [ Links ]

______. Gattegno mathematics text-book 4: Fractions, decimals, and percentages. New York: Educational Solutions, 1970c. [ Links ]

______. What we owe children: The subordination of teaching to learning. New York: Avon, 1970d. [ Links ]

______. In the beginning there were no words: The universe of babies. New York: Educational Solutions, 1973. [ Links ]

______. The science of education: Part 1: Theoretical considerations. New York: Educational Solutions, 1987. [ Links ]

______. Arithmetic: A teacher’s introduction to the Cuisenaire-Gattegno method of teaching arithmetic New York: Educational Solutions Worldwide, 2009/1960. [ Links ]

GATTEGNO, G. C.; HOFFMAN, M. R. Handbook of activities for the teaching of mathematics at the elementary school. New York: Human Education, 1976. [ Links ]

GILLINGS, R. J. Mathematics in the time of the pharaohs. Mineola, New York: Dover, 1972/1982. [ Links ]

HUNT, J. H. et al. Levels of participatory conception of fractional quantity along a purposefully sequenced series of equal sharing tasks: Stu's trajectory. Journal of Mathematical Behavior, v. 41, p. 45-67, 3/1/March 2016 2016. ISSN 0732-3123. Disponível em: <https://login.proxy.libraries.rutgers.edu/login?url=http://search.ebscohost.com/login.aspx?direct=true&db=edselp&AN=S0732312315300122&site=eds-live>. [ Links ]

JORDAN, N. C.; GLUTTING, J.; RAMINENI, C. The importance of number sense to mathematics achievement in first and third grades. Learning and Individual Differences, v. 20, p. 82-88, 1/1/2010 2010. ISSN 1041-6080. Disponível em: <https://login.proxy.libraries.rutgers.edu/login?url=https://search.ebscohost.com/login.aspx?direct=true&db=edselp&AN=S1041608009000533&site=eds-live>. [ Links ]

KALCHMAN, M.; MOSS, J.; CASE, R. Psychological models for the development of mathematical understanding: Rational numbers and functions. In: CARVER, S. M. e KLAHR, D. (Ed.). Cognition and instruction: Twenty-five years of progress. Mahwah, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum., 2001. p.1-38. [ Links ]

KERSLAKE, D. Fractions: Children’s strategies and errors. Windsor, England: NEER-NELSON, 1986. [ Links ]

KIEREN, T. E. On the mathematical, cognitive and instructional foundations of rational number. In: LESH, R. A. (Ed.). Number and measurement. Columbus, Ohio: ERIC Clearinghouse for Science, Mathematics, and Environmental Education, 1976. p.101-144. [ Links ]

______. The rational number construct-Its elements and mechanisms. In: KIEREN, T. E. (Ed.). Recent research on number learning. Columbus, Ohio: ERIC Clearinghouse for Science, Mathematics, and Environmental Education, 1980. p.125-150. [ Links ]

______. Rational and fractional numbers: From quotient fields to recursive understanding. In: CARPENTER, T. P.;FENNEMA, E., et al (Ed.). Rational numbers: An integration of research. New Jersey: Erlbaum., 1993. p.49-84. [ Links ]

LAMON, S. J. Presenting and representing: From fractions to rational numbers. In: CUOCO, A. e CURCIO, F. (Ed.). The Roles of Representations in School Mathematics - 2001 Yearbook. Reston: National Council of Teachers of Mathematics, 2001. p.146-168. [ Links ]

______. Rational numbers and proportional reasoning: Toward a theoretical framework for research. In: LESTER, J. F. K. (Ed.). Second handbook of research on mathematics teaching and learning: A Project of the National Council of Teachers of Mathematics. Charlotte, NC: Information Age, 2007. p .629-667. [ Links ]

______. Teaching fractions and ratios for understanding: Essential content knowledge and instructional strategies for teachers. 3rd. New York: Routledge, 2012. ISBN 978-0805852103. [ Links ]

LIN, C.-Y. et al. Preservice Teachers’ Conceptual and Procedural Knowledge of Fraction Operations: A Comparative Study of the United States and Taiwan. School Science and Mathematics, v. 113, n. 1, p. 41-51, 01/01/ 2013. ISSN 0036-6803. Disponível em: <https://login.proxy.libraries.rutgers.edu/login?url=http://search.ebscohost.com/login.aspx?direct=true&db=eric&AN=EJ1009005&site=eds-live http://dx.doi.org/10.1111/j.1949-8594.2012.00173.x>. [ Links ]

MA, L. Knowing and teaching elementary mathematics: Teachers' understanding of fundamental mathematics in China and the United States. Mahwah: Lawrence Erlbaum, 1999. [ Links ]

MACK, N. K. Learning fractions with understanding: Building on informal knowledge. Journal for Research in Mathematics Education, v. 21, n. 1, p. 16-32, 1990. [ Links ]

______. Confounding whole-number and fraction concepts when building on informal knowledge. Journal for Research in Mathematics Education, v. 26, n. 5, p. 422-441, 1995. [ Links ]

MAHER, C. A.; YANKELEWITZ, D., Eds. Children’s reasoning while building fraction ideas. Boston: Senseed. 2017. [ Links ]

MARTIN, W. G.; STRUTCHENS, M. E.; ELLIOTT, P. C. The learning of mathematics. Reston, VA: National Council of Teachers of Mathematics, 2007. [ Links ]

MEIRA, L. Making Sense of Instructional Devices: The Emergence of Transparency in Mathematical Activity. Journal for Research in Mathematics Education, v. 29, n. 2, p. 121-142, 1998. ISSN 00218251, 19452306. Disponível em: <http://www.jstor.org/stable/749895>. [ Links ]

MORRIS, A. K. A teaching experiment: Introducing fourth graders to fractions from the viewpoint of measuring quantities using Davydov’s mathematics curriculum. Focus on Learning Problems in Mathematics, v. 22, n. 2, p. 32-83, 2000. [ Links ]

MOSES, R. P.; COBB, C. E., JR. Radical equations: Math literacy and civil rights. Boston: Beacon, 2001. [ Links ]

NATIONAL GOVERNORS ASSOCIATION CENTER FOR BEST PRACTICES; COUNCIL OF CHIEF STATE SCHOOL OFFICERS. Common core state standards for mathematics Washington, DC: National Governors Association Center for Best Practices, Council of Chief State School Officers 2010. [ Links ]

NATIONAL MATHEMATICS ADVISORY PANEL. Foundations for success: The final report of the National Mathematics Advisory Panel. US Department of Education. Washington, DC. 2008 [ Links ]

NI, Y.; ZHOU, Y.-D. Teaching and learning fraction and rational numbers: The origins and implications of whole number bias. Educational Psychologist, v. 40, n. 1, p. 27-52, 2005. [ Links ]

OAKES, J. et al. Detracking: The social construction of ability, cultural politics, and resistance to reform. Teachers College Record, v. 98, n. 3, p. 482-510, 1997. [ Links ]

OLANOFF, D.; LO, J.-J.; TOBIAS, J. M. Mathematical content knowledge for teaching elementary mathematics: A focus on fractions. The Mathematics Enthusiast, v. 11, n. 2, p. 267-310, 2014. [ Links ]

PATAHUDDIN, S. M.; USMAN, H. B.; RAMFUL, A. Affordances from Number Lines in Fractions Instruction: Students’ Interpretation of Teacher’s Intentions. International Journal of Science and Mathematics Education, February 14 2017. ISSN 1573-1774. Disponível em: <https://doi.org/10.1007/s10763-017-9800-z>. [ Links ]

POWELL, A. B. Caleb Gattegno (1911-1988): A famous mathematics educator from Africa? Revista Brasileira de História da Matemática, p. 199-209, 2007. [ Links ]

RESNIKOFF, H. L.; WELLS JR., R. O. Mathematics in civilization. In: (Ed.). New York: Dover, 1984/1973. [ Links ]

RITTLE-JOHNSON, B.; SIEGLER, R. S.; ALIBALI, M. W. Developing conceptual understanding and procedural skill in mathematics: An iterative process. Journal of Educational Psychology, v. 93, n. 2, p. 346-362, 2001. [ Links ]

ROQUE, T. História da matemática: Uma visão crítica, desfazendo mitos e lendas. Rio de Janeiro: Zahar, 2012. [ Links ]

SCHMITTAU, J. Cultural-historical theory and mathematics education. In: KOZULIN, A.;GINDIS, B., et al (Ed.). Vygotsky’s educational theory in cultural context. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge, 2003. p.225-245. [ Links ]

______. Vygotskian theory and mathematics education: Resolving the conceptual-procedural dichotomy. European Journal of Psychology of Education, v. XIX, n. 1, p. 19-43, 2004. [ Links ]

SCHMITTAU, J.; MORRIS, A. The development of algebra in the elementary mathematics curriculum of V.V. Davydov. The Mathematics Educator, v. 8, n. 1, p. 60-87, 2004. [ Links ]

SIEGLER, R. S. et al. Early Predictors of High School Mathematics Achievement. Psychological Science, v. 23, n. 7, p. 691-697, 2012. Disponível em: <http://journals.sagepub.com/doi/abs/10.1177/0956797612440101>. [ Links ]

SIEGLER, R. S.; LORTIE-FORGUES, H. Conceptual knowledge of fraction arithmetic. Journal of Educational Psychology, v. 107, n. 3, p. 909-918, 2015. [ Links ]

SIEGLER, R. S.; THOMPSON, C. A.; SCHNEIDER, M. An integrated theory of whole number and fractions development. Cognitive Psychology, v. 62, n. 4, p. 273-296, 6// 2011. ISSN 0010-0285. Disponível em: <http://www.sciencedirect.com/science/article/pii/S001002851100003X>. [ Links ]

STRUIK, D. J. A concise history of mathematics. 3rd Revised. New York: Dover, 1967/1948. [ Links ]

SWELLER, J. Cognitive load theory, learning difficulty, and instructional design. Learning and instruction, v. 4, n. 4, p. 295-312, 1994. ISSN 0959-4752. [ Links ]

SWELLER, J.; VAN MERRIENBOER, J. J.; PAAS, F. G. Cognitive architecture and instructional design. Educational psychology review, v. 10, n. 3, p. 251-296, 1998. ISSN 1040-726X. [ Links ]

TORBEYNS, J. et al. Bridging the gap: Fraction understanding is central to mathematics achievement in students from three different continents. Learning and Instruction, v. 37, p. 5-13, 6// 2015. ISSN 0959-4752. Disponível em: <http://www.sciencedirect.com/science/article/pii/S0959475214000255>. [ Links ]

TUCKER, A. Fractions and units in everyday life. In: MADISON, B. L. e STEEN, L. A. (Ed.). Calculation vs. context: Quantitative literacy and its implications for teacher education. Washington, DC: Mathematical Association of America, 2008. p.75-86. [ Links ]

TZUR, R. An integrated study of children's construction of improper fractions and the teacher's role in promoting that learning. Journal for Research in Mathematics Education, v. 30, n. 4, p. 390-416, 1999. [ Links ]

VERGNAUD, G. Multiplicative structures. In: LESH, R. e LANDAU, M. (Ed.). Acquisition of mathematical concepts and processes. New York: Academic, 1983. p.127-174. [ Links ]

VYGOTSKY, L. S. Mind in society: The development of higher psychological processes. Cambridge, MA: Harvard, 1978/1930. [ Links ]

WANG, C. et al. Effect of abacus training on executive function development and underlying neural correlates in Chinese children. Human Brain Mapping, v. 38, n. 10, p. 5234-5249, 2017. [ Links ]

WILLINGHAM, D. T. Is it true that some people just can’t do math? American Educator, v. 34, n. 4, p. 14-19, 39, 2009. [ Links ]

WU, H.-H. How to prepare students for algebra. American Educator, v. 25, n. 2, p. 1-7, 2001. [ Links ]

______. What’s sophisticated about elementary mathematics? Plenty—That’s why elementary schools need math teachers. American Educator, v. 33, n. 3, p. 4-14, 2009. [ Links ]

ZACK, V.; GRAVES, B. Making mathematical meaning through dialogue: "Once you think of it, the z minus three seems pretty weird". Educational Studies in Mathematics, v. 46, n. 1-3, p. 229-271, 2001. [ Links ]

ZEVENBERGEN, R. The construction of a mathematical habitus: implications of ability grouping in the middle years. Journal of Curriculum Studies, v. 37, n. 5, p. 607-619, 2005. [ Links ]

Received: September 15, 2017; Accepted: February 16, 2018

Creative Commons License This is an Open Access article distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution License, which permits unrestricted use, distribution, and reproduction in any medium, provided the original work is properly cited.